TRANSLATE THIS ARTICLE
Integral World: Exploring Theories of Everything
An independent forum for a critical discussion of the integral philosophy of Ken Wilber
Ken Wilber: Thought as Passion, SUNY 2003Frank Visser, graduated as a psychologist of culture and religion, founded IntegralWorld in 1997. He worked as production manager for various publishing houses and as service manager for various internet companies and lives in Amsterdam. Books: Ken Wilber: Thought as Passion (SUNY, 2003), and The Corona Conspiracy: Combatting Disinformation about the Coronavirus (Kindle, 2020).
SEE MORE ESSAYS WRITTEN BY FRANK VISSER

NOTE: This essay contains AI-generated content
Check out more of these AI-generated essays

‘A Universe in Consciousness’

The Merits and Shortcomings of
Bernardo Kastrup's Philosophy of Idealism

Frank Visser / ChatGPT-4

Me to ChatGPT:

  • Please write an essay on the merits and shortcomings of Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy of idealism. How does he compare to other idealists? How is he viewed by contemporary philosophers?

Follow-up questions:

Bernardo Kastrup
Bernardo Kastrup: ‘There is
only cosmic consciousness.’
Metaphysical Speculations
  • For those who don't know him, please introduce Bernardo Kastrup to my readers.
  • Please summarize Kastrup's theory for a layman audience if that's possible.
  • Please elaborate on the perceived shortcomings[1] and how Kastrup refutes those.
  • Please elaborate on the precise nature of "Mind-at-large" as conceptualized by Kastrup. Is it a God-like superbeing or a more distributed mind?
  • Kastrup compares individual minds to the multiple personalities or "alters" someone suffering from a dissociative identity disorder can experience. How valid is this metaphor from psychopathology for the elucidation the nature of consciousness and has it been criticized?
  • Here's a strong criticism from a skeptic philosopher: "Holy crap. So we are now positing that the entire universe 'suffers' from a multiple personality disorder because we need to solve a non-problem that we created ourselves out of stubbornly postulating that there is something special and quasi-magical about consciousness. — Massimo Pigliucci". Please comment.
  • In my understanding, in idealistic philosophy the distinction between perception and imagination gets blurred. We perceive the real world; we imagine an ideal world. But calling reality "ideal" (if not in our own minds but in a universal Mind) does not help clarifying this distinction. Please comment.
  • Why do we need the hypothesis of a Universal Mind at all?
  • But why, if idealism fails at the individual level, would it succeed at the cosmic level instead? This seems to me a sleight of hand that causes more problems than it solves. We associate mind and consciousness normally with subjects and biological organisms, and the cosmos is not known to have these features—as far as I can tell.
  • But surely the cosmos doesn't depend on us? There was a time there were no humans on earth, or even life, was the cosmos any different?
  • This is the idealist's sleight of hand: first the reality of the world is denied, but with the unlikely hypothesis of Mind-at-large it is re-affirmed again. Why not affirm it in the first place?
  • It seems to me realism has a mind-problem, but idealism has a reality-problem.
  • Appendix: Bernardo Kastrup's Dissertation

ChatGPT:

Introduction

Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy of idealism offers a refreshing and thought-provoking perspective on the nature of reality. He builds on the concepts of idealism, asserting that the entire universe is mental and that reality consists only of conscious experiences. In this comprehensive analysis, we will explore the merits and shortcomings of Kastrup's philosophy, compare him to other idealists, and examine how he is viewed by contemporary philosophers.

Section I: Merits of Kastrup's Idealism

A. Addressing Hard Problem of Consciousness

Kastrup's idealism directly tackles the hard problem of consciousness, arguing that mental phenomena cannot be fully explained by physical processes. By positing that everything is mind, he circumvents the problem by making consciousness primary.

B. Unifying Outlook

Kastrup's philosophy emphasizes the interconnectedness of all phenomena, reducing the apparent dualism between mind and matter. This view allows for a unifying perspective on science and spirituality.

C. Non-Reductionism

Unlike some materialist perspectives, Kastrup's philosophy avoids reducing mental states to mere brain states. This allows for a richer understanding of conscious experience and acknowledges the intrinsic value of subjective experience.

Section II: Shortcomings of Kastrup's Idealism

A. Lack of Empirical Evidence

Kastrup's idealism has been criticized for lacking empirical evidence. Critics argue that without concrete data to support the idea that everything is mental, the theory remains abstract and unverifiable.

B. Difficulty in Explaining Inter-subjective Reality

Another criticism focuses on the challenge in explaining how different individual minds can share a common, inter-subjective reality. If everything is mind, the problem of understanding consensus reality becomes complex.

C. Potential Solipsism

The idea that all existence is mind can inadvertently lead to solipsism, a belief that only one's mind is sure to exist. Though Kastrup explicitly rejects solipsism, critics claim that his idealism might not successfully escape this problem.

Section III: Comparison to Other Idealists

Kastrup's philosophy shares similarities with other forms of idealism, such as Bishop Berkeley's subjective idealism and Hegel's absolute idealism. However, Kastrup emphasizes a more monistic and less dualistic interpretation, aligning closer to Eastern philosophies like Advaita Vedanta. He also focuses on experiential, rather than rational, approaches, setting his work apart from more traditional Western idealists.

Section IV: Reception by Contemporary Philosophers

Contemporary philosophers are divided in their reception of Kastrup's idealism. Some see it as a courageous departure from materialistic paradigms, providing new insights into the nature of reality. Others criticize it as overly speculative, lacking in rigorous argumentation and empirical support.

Prominent philosophers within the fields of consciousness studies and metaphysics have engaged with Kastrup's ideas, leading to lively debates and discussions. The broader impact of his philosophy, however, has yet to be fully assessed within mainstream philosophical circles.

Conclusion

Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy of idealism offers a unique and provocative perspective on the nature of reality. By emphasizing the primacy of mind, it challenges conventional materialistic views and opens new avenues for understanding consciousness and existence. While the merits of his approach are numerous, including the unifying outlook and non-reductionism, shortcomings such as lack of empirical evidence and difficulties in explaining inter-subjective reality present significant challenges.

Kastrup's philosophy stands in dialogue with both Eastern and Western traditions of idealism, carving out its unique space. The reception by contemporary philosophers is mixed, reflecting the complex and controversial nature of his ideas. Further exploration and critical examination of Kastrup's idealism will undoubtedly contribute to the ongoing discourse on the fundamental nature of reality and consciousness.

For those who don't know him, please introduce Bernardo Kastrup to my readers.

Bernardo Kastrup is a contemporary philosopher and computer scientist whose work focuses on the nature of reality, consciousness, and the mind-body problem. He is one of the leading proponents of metaphysical idealism, a philosophical stance that posits consciousness as the fundamental reality, with the physical world being a manifestation or expression of this underlying consciousness.

Here's a more detailed introduction to Kastrup and his work:

Background and Education

Kastrup has a background in both philosophy and science. He holds a Ph.D. in Computer Engineering with specializations in artificial intelligence and reconfigurable computing. He also has a Ph.D. in Philosophy, focusing on ontology and the philosophy of mind. His interdisciplinary background allows him to approach philosophical questions with a blend of scientific rigor and metaphysical insight.

Philosophy and Writings

Kastrup's philosophical work centers on the idea that the universe is fundamentally mental in nature. He argues against materialism, the view that physical matter is the primary reality, and instead posits that everything arises from a universal consciousness.

He has written several books on this subject, including "Why Materialism Is Baloney," "The Idea of the World," and "More Than Allegory." His writings are known for their clarity and accessibility, making complex philosophical ideas understandable to a general audience.

The Concept of Mind-at-Large

One of Kastrup's key ideas is the concept of "Mind-at-Large," a universal consciousness from which individual human minds emerge as dissociated parts. He likens our individual consciousness to alters within a broader, cosmic mind. This perspective leads to the metaphor of the physical world as a "shared dream".

Contributions to Science and Technology

In addition to his philosophical work, Kastrup has made contributions to the fields of computer science and artificial intelligence. His technical expertise informs his philosophical inquiries, particularly in the areas of cognition, consciousness, and the nature of reality.

Public Engagement

Kastrup is an active public intellectual, engaging with audiences through lectures, interviews, and online platforms. He is a vocal critic of materialism and a proponent of a more consciousness-centric understanding of reality.

Conclusion

Bernardo Kastrup is a thought-provoking philosopher whose work challenges conventional wisdom about the nature of reality. By arguing for a universe grounded in consciousness rather than physical matter, he offers a radical rethinking of the mind-body problem and the relationship between the mental and physical worlds. His writings provide an accessible entry point for those interested in exploring these profound philosophical questions.

Please summarize Kastrup's theory for a layman audience if that's possible.

Bernardo Kastrup's theory is a form of philosophical idealism, and it can be a bit complex, but I'll do my best to break it down into simpler terms for a layman audience.

Everything is Mind:

Kastrup argues that everything in the universe is fundamentally made of consciousness or mind. Unlike the common view that the physical world exists independently of our thoughts and feelings, Kastrup's theory posits that everything we perceive is a manifestation of a universal consciousness.

Individual Minds are "Alters":

According to Kastrup, individual minds (like yours and mine) are like separate personalities or "alters" within a larger, universal mind. Think of it as different waves in the same ocean. Each wave is unique but made of the same water.

The Physical World is a Shared Dream:

Kastrup likens our shared reality to a collective dream. The physical objects we see, like tables and chairs, are how our individual minds interpret the underlying mental reality. Different people might perceive these objects slightly differently, just as different people might describe a shared dream in various ways.

Brains are Translators, Not Generators, of Consciousness:

In mainstream science, the brain is often thought of as the generator of consciousness. Kastrup, however, sees the brain as a translator or decoder of consciousness. When we look at someone's brain activity, we're seeing a physical representation of their inner thoughts and feelings.

No "Hard Problem of Consciousness":

In philosophy, the "hard problem of consciousness" is the question of how physical processes in the brain give rise to the subjective experience of being. Kastrup's theory avoids this problem by positing that everything is already consciousness, so there's no need to explain how consciousness arises from non-conscious matter.

Survival and Evolution Shape Perception:

Kastrup also argues that the way we perceive the world is shaped by evolution and the need to survive. We don't see the world as it truly is (as pure consciousness) but in a way that helps us navigate and thrive in it.

Quantum Physics Supports Idealism:

Kastrup suggests that some interpretations of quantum physics, where particles exist in a state of potentiality until observed, align with his view that the physical world is a manifestation of consciousness.

In summary, Bernardo Kastrup's theory presents a view where everything is fundamentally mind or consciousness. The physical world is a shared dream or interpretation, and individual minds are like separate waves in the same ocean of universal consciousness. It's a perspective that challenges many common assumptions about reality and offers a different way to understand our existence and the nature of the universe.

Please elaborate on the perceived shortcomings[1] and how Kastrup refutes those.

Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy of idealism has faced several criticisms, each with its unique complexity. Below, we will elaborate on the perceived shortcomings and explore how Kastrup has sought to refute or address these criticisms.

A. Lack of Empirical Evidence

Criticism: Kastrup's assertion that all reality is fundamentally mental has been criticized for lacking empirical evidence. Critics argue that, without concrete scientific support, the idea remains abstract and speculative.

Kastrup's Refutation: Kastrup argues that his idealism is not without empirical basis. He refers to certain interpretations of quantum mechanics that might align with his worldview, such as the observer effect, where the act of observation alters the behavior of quantum particles. He posits that consciousness isn't just a product of the brain but a fundamental aspect of reality, something supported indirectly by the inexplicable nature of conscious experience within a purely physicalist framework.

B. Difficulty in Explaining Inter-subjective Reality

Criticism: A major challenge to Kastrup's philosophy is explaining how different individual minds can share a common, inter-subjective reality. If everything is mental, how do we all agree on a shared reality?

Kastrup's Refutation: Kastrup offers the concept of a "Mind-at-large," suggesting that individual minds are localized expressions of a broader, universal consciousness. He likens individual experiences to whirlpools within an expansive ocean of consciousness. This metaphor helps explain how individual experiences can coexist within a unified, inter-subjective reality, albeit without entirely dissolving the problem.

C. Potential Solipsism

Criticism: The idea that all existence is mind can inadvertently lead to solipsism, where only one's mind is sure to exist. Critics say that Kastrup's idealism might fall into this trap.

Kastrup's Refutation: Kastrup explicitly denies solipsism, arguing that individual consciousnesses are connected to a greater, collective mental reality. The "Mind-at-large" concept, as mentioned earlier, provides a framework for understanding how individual minds are part of a larger whole. He emphasizes that, although reality is mental, it does not mean that it is confined to individual subjectivity.

D. Incompatibility with Physical Sciences

Criticism: Some critics argue that Kastrup's idealism conflicts with the established paradigms of physical sciences, such as the belief in an objective, external world.

Kastrup's Refutation: Kastrup counters this by stating that his philosophy doesn't negate the existence of an external world but reinterprets it. He argues that the external world exists as a shared mental construct within the "Mind-at-large." This, he believes, does not undermine the empirical discoveries of science but provides a new ontological perspective that accommodates both subjective experience and objective observations.

Conclusion

Bernardo Kastrup's philosophy of idealism brings intriguing insights into the nature of reality but also faces substantial criticisms. While Kastrup has crafted refutations that align with his philosophical framework, not all critics are satisfied with his responses. The debate around his philosophy reflects broader discussions in metaphysics and consciousness studies, highlighting the complexity and ongoing challenges in understanding the nature of reality and our place within it.

Please elaborate on the precise nature of "Mind-at-large" as conceptualized by Kastrup. Is it a God-like superbeing or a more distributed mind?

Bernardo Kastrup's concept of "Mind-at-large" is a central part of his philosophical idealism, and it serves to address some of the criticisms and shortcomings associated with the idea that all reality is fundamentally mental. The "Mind-at-large" is not described as a God-like superbeing in Kastrup's work, but rather as a more distributed, impersonal form of consciousness.

The Distributed Nature of "Mind-at-Large"

Kastrup's "Mind-at-large" can be understood as a unifying field of consciousness that underlies all individual experiences. It's a foundational and universal mental layer that connects all individual minds, but it doesn't possess attributes such as intentionality, personality, or self-awareness as a traditional conception of God might.

A. Whirlpools Metaphor

Kastrup often uses the metaphor of whirlpools within an expansive ocean to describe the relationship between individual minds and the "Mind-at-large." In this analogy, individual consciousnesses are akin to whirlpools, localized and distinct, yet part of the larger ocean. The ocean itself represents the "Mind-at-large," a continuous and unbroken field of consciousness.

B. Not a Personal Deity

The concept does not imply a personal or anthropomorphic deity that has desires, intentions, or specific plans. Rather, it's an abstract, universal mental reality that exists beyond personal attributes.

C. Compatibility with Individual Minds

By conceiving of a "Mind-at-large," Kastrup aims to explain how individual, private experiences can exist within a shared, inter-subjective reality. The "Mind-at-large" functions as the background or substrate from which individual minds emerge and to which they remain connected.

D. Implications for Solipsism

The notion of "Mind-at-large" helps Kastrup avoid the pitfall of solipsism by positing a collective mental reality that is not confined to individual subjectivity. The interconnectedness emphasized in this concept ensures that individual minds are not isolated entities but part of a grander, universal mind.

Conclusion

Bernardo Kastrup's concept of "Mind-at-large" is central to his philosophical outlook, offering a nuanced and abstract view of consciousness that avoids anthropomorphizing or reducing it to individual subjectivity. Far from a God-like superbeing, the "Mind-at-large" is portrayed as a distributed and impersonal field of consciousness that underlies and connects all individual experiences. This concept, while intriguing, is also complex and has sparked considerable debate and discussion, reflecting the ongoing challenges and mysteries of consciousness and reality.

Kastrup compares individual minds to the multiple personalities or "alters" someone suffering from a dissociative identity disorder can experience. How valid is this metaphor from psychopathology for the elucidation the nature of consciousness and has it been criticized?

Bernardo Kastrup has indeed employed the metaphor of dissociative identity disorder (DID), formerly known as multiple personality disorder, to explain the relationship between individual minds and a universal consciousness or "Mind-at-large." This metaphor is a central part of his philosophical approach to consciousness, and it serves to illustrate complex and abstract ideas. Here's an overview of the metaphor and its reception:

Kastrup's Metaphor: Dissociative Identity Disorder

The Metaphor: Kastrup uses the phenomenon of DID to liken individual human consciousness to dissociated "alters" within a more extensive, universal consciousness. In DID, a single mind seems to fracture into multiple, often independent personalities or identities, each with its unique memories, behaviors, and experiences. Kastrup's metaphor suggests that each human being is like a dissociated alter of the universal mind, experiencing a localized and limited perspective within a broader conscious reality.

The Implications: This metaphor serves to illustrate how individual minds can be both distinct and unified within a more extensive consciousness. It challenges materialist assumptions about the nature of the mind and offers a novel way of thinking about the relationship between individual experience and reality.

Criticisms and Challenges

Psychopathological Basis: Some critics may argue that using a psychopathological condition as a metaphor for the nature of consciousness might be inappropriate or overly simplistic. DID is a complex and contested diagnosis, and its mechanisms are not fully understood.

Metaphysical Leap: Others might contend that the metaphor requires a significant metaphysical leap from the known characteristics of DID to the speculative notion of a universal consciousness. The metaphor may vividly illustrate Kastrup's ideas but does not necessarily provide empirical support for them.

Lack of Scientific Grounding: Scientists and philosophers committed to a materialist or physicalist perspective may challenge the metaphor on the grounds that it lacks grounding in scientific observation or methodology. They might see it as a creative but ultimately unverifiable conceptualization.

Conclusion

Kastrup's metaphor of DID to explain the relationship between individual minds and a universal consciousness is a provocative and imaginative way to articulate complex philosophical ideas. It offers a novel perspective that resonates with some aspects of human experience and various spiritual and philosophical traditions.

However, the metaphor also faces criticisms and challenges, especially from those who see it as an oversimplification or as lacking empirical grounding. The validity of the metaphor likely depends on one's broader philosophical commitments and interpretive stance. It serves as a vivid illustration of Kastrup's ideas, but like many metaphors in philosophy, it may not be universally convincing or accepted.

Here's a strong criticism from a skeptic philosopher: "Holy crap. So we are now positing that the entire universe 'suffers' from a multiple personality disorder because we need to solve a non-problem that we created ourselves out of stubbornly postulating that there is something special and quasi-magical about consciousness. — Massimo Pigliucci"[2] Please comment.

Massimo Pigliucci's criticism of Bernardo Kastrup's theory is a strong and colorful one, reflecting a skepticism that is common among those who adhere to a more materialistic or physicalist view of the world.

The Critique of "Multiple Personality Disorder":

Pigliucci's comparison of the universe to a patient with multiple personality disorder is a metaphorical way to express his disbelief in the idea that individual minds are like separate personalities within a universal consciousness. He seems to find this concept implausible and perhaps overly complex.

The "Non-Problem" of Consciousness:

Pigliucci refers to the hard problem of consciousness as a "non-problem" that has been created unnecessarily. This reflects a view that consciousness is not something special or mysterious that needs a unique explanation. For those who believe that consciousness can be fully explained by physical processes in the brain, the idea of positing a universal consciousness to explain individual experiences might seem unnecessary or even absurd.

The Accusation of "Quasi-Magical" Thinking:

By referring to consciousness as "quasi-magical," Pigliucci is criticizing the idea that consciousness is something fundamentally different from other physical phenomena. This might be seen as a rejection of any form of dualism, where mind and matter are considered separate substances.

A Clash of Worldviews:

At its core, this criticism reflects a deep philosophical divide between materialism, which sees the world as fundamentally physical, and idealism, which sees it as fundamentally mental or conscious. Kastrup's theory is firmly in the idealist camp, while Pigliucci's criticism comes from a materialist perspective.

A Matter of Perspective:

It's worth noting that what might seem like a "non-problem" or "quasi-magical" from one philosophical perspective might be a serious issue or a profound insight from another. The debate between idealism and materialism is longstanding and unlikely to be resolved easily.

In summary, Massimo Pigliucci's criticism of Bernardo Kastrup's theory is a forceful expression of a materialist viewpoint. It highlights fundamental disagreements about the nature of consciousness and reality. Whether one finds Kastrup's theory compelling or Pigliucci's criticism convincing may depend largely on underlying philosophical commitments and intuitions about the nature of the mind and the world.

In my understanding, in idealistic philosophy the distinction between perception and imagination gets blurred. We perceive the real world; we imagine an ideal world. But calling reality "ideal" (if not in our own minds but in a universal Mind) does not help clarifying this distinction. Please comment.

The distinction between perception and imagination, and the relationship between the real and the ideal, is indeed a complex and nuanced issue in idealistic philosophy. Here's an exploration of some of the themes you've raised:

Perception vs. Imagination:

In a materialistic worldview, perception is often understood as the mind's interaction with an external, physical reality, while imagination is seen as an internal mental process that may or may not correspond to anything real. In idealism, both perception and imagination are seen as mental phenomena, but they are not necessarily the same thing. Perception might be understood as a direct experience of a shared reality, while imagination might be seen as a more private, creative mental activity.

The Real and the Ideal:

The term "ideal" in idealism doesn't necessarily refer to something that is perfect or desirable (as in "an ideal world"). Rather, it refers to the idea that reality is fundamentally mental or conscious in nature. This doesn't mean that everything we imagine is real, or that there is no difference between reality and fantasy. It means that what we call "real" is a particular kind of mental phenomenon, one that is shared and consistent across different minds.

Universal Mind:

Some forms of idealism posit a universal Mind or consciousness that encompasses all individual minds. In this view, our individual perceptions might be seen as particular perspectives within this universal Mind, while our imaginations might be seen as more private, less constrained mental activities. The distinction between perception and imagination is not necessarily blurred; it's just understood differently.

Challenges and Criticisms:

The idea that reality is fundamentally mental can be challenging to grasp, and it raises many questions. How do we distinguish between shared perceptions and private imaginations? How do we account for the apparent stability and consistency of the physical world? How do we explain the relationship between individual minds and the universal Mind? Different idealistic philosophies offer different answers to these questions, and not everyone finds these answers satisfying.

Implications for Knowledge and Ethics:

If reality is ideal in nature, this has profound implications for how we understand knowledge, truth, and ethics. What we call "objective" might be understood as what is shared and consistent within the universal Mind, while what is "subjective" might be seen as more individual and variable. This can lead to a different understanding of what it means to know something, what it means for something to be true, and what it means to live a good or ethical life.

In summary, idealism does not necessarily blur the distinction between perception and imagination, but it does understand these concepts in a different way than materialism does. The idea that reality is ideal or mental in nature can be both profound and perplexing, and it raises many questions that are central to philosophy, science, and ethics. Whether one finds idealism compelling or confusing may depend on one's underlying intuitions, experiences, and philosophical commitments.

Why do we need the hypothesis of a Universal Mind at all?

The hypothesis of a Universal Mind is not something that everyone agrees is necessary, but it has been posited by some idealistic philosophers for several reasons:

Explaining Shared Reality:

If everything is mental in nature, how do we explain the fact that we all seem to live in a shared, consistent reality? The idea of a Universal Mind can provide an answer to this question. Our individual minds might be seen as particular perspectives within a greater Mind that encompasses all of reality.

Solving the Hard Problem of Consciousness:

Some proponents of the Universal Mind hypothesis see it as a way to address the so-called "hard problem" of consciousness, which is the question of why and how physical processes in the brain give rise to the subjective experience of being. If everything is fundamentally mental, then consciousness is not something that needs to be explained as arising from something else; it's the fundamental nature of reality itself.

Addressing the Problem of Interaction:

In dualistic philosophies that posit both mental and physical substances, there's a problem of explaining how these two fundamentally different kinds of things can interact. The Universal Mind hypothesis avoids this problem by positing that everything is of the same substance, namely, mind.

Ethical and Spiritual Implications:

Some see the idea of a Universal Mind as having profound ethical and spiritual implications. If we are all part of a greater Mind, then we are all interconnected in a deep way, and this can lead to a sense of responsibility, compassion, and reverence for all of life.

Simplicity and Parsimony:

From a philosophical standpoint, the idea of a Universal Mind might be seen as a more parsimonious explanation for the nature of reality. Instead of positing multiple substances (like mind and matter) or multiple levels of reality, everything is explained in terms of a single substance or principle.

Challenges and Criticisms:

It's worth noting that the idea of a Universal Mind is not without its challenges and criticisms. Some argue that it's an unnecessary hypothesis, that it raises more questions than it answers, or that it's too vague or metaphysical to be meaningful or testable.

In summary, the hypothesis of a Universal Mind is posited by some as a way to explain the nature of reality, consciousness, and our experience of a shared world. It's seen by some as a profound and elegant solution to philosophical problems, and by others as an unnecessary or problematic hypothesis. Whether one finds the idea compelling depends on one's underlying philosophical views, questions, and concerns.

But why, if idealism fails at the individual level, would it succeed at the cosmic level instead? This seems to me a sleight of hand that causes more problems than it solves. We associate mind and consciousness normally with subjects and biological organisms, and the cosmos is not known to have these features—as far as I can tell.

Your skepticism about extending idealism from the individual level to the cosmic level reflects a common critique of some forms of objective idealism. The idea of a cosmic mind or "Mind-at-large" does indeed raise a number of questions and challenges, some of which you've pointed out.

Here's a breakdown of some key issues and how proponents of objective idealism like Kastrup might respond:

The Challenge: Extending Mind to the Cosmos

Association with Organisms: As you noted, we typically associate mind and consciousness with individual organisms that have specific biological features, such as brains and nervous systems. Extending the concept of mind to the entire cosmos can seem counter-intuitive and at odds with our ordinary understanding of consciousness.

Lack of Cosmic Features: The cosmos as a whole does not exhibit the features we normally associate with consciousness, such as intentionality, self-awareness, or the capacity for subjective experience. How can the concept of a cosmic mind make sense given this lack of apparent evidence?

Explanatory Power: Does the idea of a cosmic mind actually solve any problems or explain anything about the nature of reality, or does it merely introduce new mysteries and complexities?

Potential Responses from Objective Idealists:

Reconceptualizing Mind: Proponents of objective idealism may argue that our conventional understanding of mind is too narrow. They might claim that consciousness is a more fundamental aspect of reality that doesn't depend on specific biological features.

Metaphysical Simplicity: Objective idealists like Kastrup might argue that their view offers a more parsimonious account of reality by positing a single substance (consciousness) rather than multiple substances (e.g., mind and matter).

Addressing the Hard Problem: By placing consciousness at the core of existence, objective idealism aims to address the "hard problem" of consciousness, the challenge of explaining how subjective experience arises from physical processes.

Conclusion: Valid Concerns and Ongoing Debate

Your concerns about the extension of idealism to the cosmic level reflect valid and significant philosophical questions. Objective idealism, as a metaphysical position, necessarily involves certain assumptions and conceptual leaps that may not resonate with everyone.

The debate between idealism and other philosophical views, such as realism and materialism, continues to be an active and complex area of inquiry. Philosophers who adopt objective idealism must grapple with these challenges and provide compelling arguments and evidence to support their views.

In the end, the plausibility of objective idealism may hinge on individual intuitions, preferences for certain types of explanations, and the philosophical and empirical work done to develop and defend the position. There may be no straightforward or definitive resolution to these issues, but engaging with them can lead to a deeper understanding of the nature of mind, reality, and our place in the cosmos.

But surely the cosmos doesn't depend on us? There was a time there were no humans on earth, or even life, was the cosmos any different?

The question you're raising is a significant one in the context of idealism and the hypothesis of a Universal Mind. It touches on the nature of existence and the relationship between consciousness and the cosmos.

In an idealistic framework, the existence of the cosmos doesn't depend on human consciousness specifically, but rather on consciousness or mind more generally. The idea is not that the universe depends on human minds, but rather that the universe itself is mental in nature.

Here's how some idealists might address the question:

Universal Mind:

Some idealists posit a Universal Mind that is not dependent on human or even biological life. This Mind would have existed before there were humans or any life on Earth, and the cosmos would be a manifestation of this Mind. The physical universe as we perceive it would be a particular way that this underlying mental reality is represented or experienced.

Other Conscious Observers:

Another possibility is that the universe exists as long as there are conscious observers of some kind, not necessarily human. This could include other forms of life, either on Earth or elsewhere in the universe, that have the capacity for consciousness.

Objective Idealism:

Some forms of idealism hold that the mental nature of reality is objective and doesn't depend on individual conscious observers. In this view, the universe would exist in a mental form whether or not there are conscious beings to perceive it.

Challenges and Criticisms:

Of course, these ideas are not without their challenges and criticisms. Some argue that positing a Universal Mind or objective mental reality is metaphysical and untestable. Others might see it as an unnecessary complication, preferring a physicalist view in which the universe exists independently of mind altogether.

In summary, while the cosmos doesn't depend on human consciousness specifically, in an idealistic framework, it might be understood as depending on consciousness or mind more generally. This could be in the form of a Universal Mind, other conscious observers, or an objective mental reality. The question of how the universe existed before there were conscious beings to perceive it is a deep and challenging one that goes to the heart of the nature of existence and the relationship between mind and matter. Different philosophical perspectives will provide different answers to this question.

This is the idealist's sleight of hand: first the reality of the world is denied, but with the unlikely hypothesis of Mind-at-large it is re-affirmed again. Why not affirm it in the first place?

The criticism you're presenting is a common one directed at idealism, and it's rooted in a fundamental philosophical question: What is the nature of reality, and how can we best explain it?

Here's how both sides might articulate their positions:

Idealism's Perspective:

Nature of Consciousness: Idealists might argue that consciousness is the only thing we directly experience. Everything we know about the world comes to us through our conscious experience, so it makes sense to start with consciousness as a fundamental aspect of reality.

Solving the Hard Problem: By positing that everything is mental in nature, idealists aim to avoid the "hard problem of consciousness," which is the question of how physical processes in the brain give rise to conscious experience. If everything is mental, then there's no need to explain how consciousness arises from something non-mental.

Unity of Explanation: Some idealists might argue that their view offers a more unified and parsimonious explanation of reality. By positing a single substance (mind) rather than two (mind and matter), they aim to provide a simpler and more coherent account.

Criticism from a Realist Perspective:

Unnecessary Complexity: Critics might argue that idealism introduces unnecessary complexity by denying the reality of the physical world and then reintroducing it through the concept of a Universal Mind or Mind-at-large. Why not simply accept the physical world as real in the first place?

Lack of Evidence: Some might contend that there's no empirical evidence for a Universal Mind or Mind-at-large, making it an untestable and speculative hypothesis.

Practical Considerations: Critics might also point to the practical success of science in explaining and manipulating the physical world. This success seems to rely on treating the physical world as real and independent of mind.

Conclusion:

The debate between idealism and realism is a profound and complex one, with deep philosophical roots. Both sides have their reasons and arguments, and the question may ultimately come down to fundamental intuitions and philosophical commitments.

Idealists see their position as grounded in the primacy of consciousness and believe it offers solutions to philosophical problems like the hard problem of consciousness. Critics, on the other hand, see idealism as introducing unnecessary complexity and prefer a more straightforward affirmation of the physical world.

There's no easy resolution to this debate, and it continues to be a central and lively issue in philosophy. Different individuals may find one view or the other more compelling based on their philosophical intuitions, understanding of science, and interpretive frameworks.

It seems to be realism has a mind-problem, but idealism has a reality-problem.

That's a succinct and insightful way to frame the debate between realism and idealism, and it captures a central tension in philosophy.

Realism's Mind-Problem:

Realism, particularly physicalism, posits that the physical world is fundamental and that everything, including the mind, can be reduced to physical processes. This leads to the "hard problem of consciousness," which is the challenge of explaining how subjective experiences arise from physical processes. How does the feeling of pain, the taste of chocolate, or the experience of seeing red emerge from neural activity? This has proven to be a stubborn and perplexing problem for realists.

Idealism's Reality-Problem:

Idealism, on the other hand, starts with consciousness as fundamental and posits that everything, including the physical world, is a manifestation of mind. This leads to what you've aptly termed the "reality-problem." How does the shared, consistent, and objective world we experience arise from mind? How can we account for the existence of the physical world when no one is perceiving it? How do we explain the apparent causal interactions between physical entities? These questions present significant challenges for idealists.

Conclusion:

Both realism and idealism face profound challenges in accounting for aspects of our experience that seem intuitively real and undeniable. Realism struggles with the nature of consciousness, while idealism grapples with the nature of physical reality.

These challenges have led to various hybrid theories and nuanced positions within both camps, as philosophers attempt to navigate the complexities of mind and matter. Some propose forms of dualism, recognizing both mental and physical substances. Others explore panpsychism, the idea that consciousness is a fundamental feature of the universe, present even at the level of particles.

The debate between realism and idealism is far from settled and continues to be a fertile ground for philosophical inquiry. It's a testament to the depth and complexity of these questions that they continue to engage and challenge some of the brightest minds in philosophy.

Appendix: Bernardo Kastrup's Dissertation

Please summarize the content of Kastrup's dissertation on Analytical Idealism

Dr. Bernardo Kastrup's dissertation titled "Analytic Idealism: A consciousness-only ontology" was submitted to Radboud University Nijmegen and defended on April 29, 2019. The dissertation elaborates on a modern, analytic version of the ontology of idealism, positing that phenomenal consciousness is fundamental, and everything else in nature can be reduced to or grounded in patterns of excitation of phenomenal consciousness.

Here's a summary of the key sections and content:

Introduction (Page 12): The dissertation introduces a modern, analytic version of idealism, where phenomenal consciousness is fundamental, and everything else can be reduced to patterns of excitation within this consciousness. It aims to tackle the "decomposition problem" and address challenges like reconciling idealism with the common external world, correlations between brain activity and experience, etc.

Conflating Abstraction with Empirical Observation (Page 8): This section discusses the false mind-matter dichotomy, levels of explanatory abstraction, and dispelling the mind-matter dichotomy.

The Universe in Consciousness (Page 8): This part explores the mainstream physicalist ontology, consciousness as an irreducible property of matter, the whole universe as a unitary conscious entity, and related concepts.

On the Plausibility of Idealism: Refuting Criticisms (Page 8): This section refutes various objections to idealism, such as the felt concreteness objection, private minds objection, stand-alone world objection, and more.

There Is an 'Unconscious,' but It May Well Be Conscious (Page 9): This chapter explores the definition and gauging of consciousness, non-self-reflective experiences, dissociated experiences, and a model of dissociation.

Self-Transcendence Correlates with Brain Function Impairment (Page 9): This section discusses cerebral hypoxia, generalized physiological stress, electromagnetic impairment, trance-induced impairment, chemical impairment, physical damage, and more.

Concluding Remarks (Page 9): The conclusion summarizes the main points, including matter as the outer appearance of inner experience, the conundrum of spacetime, visualizing the ontological primitive, and future work.

Appendices (Page 9): Two appendices discuss the hermeneutic of the world and the physicalist worldview as a neurotic ego-defense mechanism.

Acknowledgments (Page 10): Dr. Kastrup thanks his supervisors, colleagues, and others who contributed to the dissertation.

The dissertation is a comprehensive exploration of analytic idealism, providing a modern interpretation and addressing various objections and misconceptions.

Bernardo's defense of his second Ph.D., Nijmegen, April 29, 2019

Imaginary conversation at this PhD ceremony: "Opponent: do I really exist for you? If you say yes, your idealism is refuted. If you say no, this ceremony loses all meaning."

NOTES

[1] See also my 3-part series on Bernardo Kastrup at www.integralworld.net:

  1. "Why Idealism is Bonkers, Some Reflections on the Philosophy of Bernardo Kastrup", November 2019
  2. "'Why the Tree Will Continue to Be', Further Musings on the Idealism of Bernardo Kastrup" , November 2019
  3. "'We don't know whether mutations are really random or not', Reflections on Randomness by Bernardo Kastrup", December 2019

Kastrup mentioned my work on an old Googlegroups forum "Metaphysical Speculations" which is now offline in his characteristic way:

[2] Massimo Pigliucci, "Does the universe suffer from multiple personalities disorder?", platofootnote.wordpress.com, December 10, 2018.

Pigliucci refers to the Scientific American Observation article "Could Multiple Personality Disorder Explain Life, the Universe and Everything?" written by Bernardo Kastrup, Adam Crabtree, Edward F. Kelly on June 18, 2018.

It is a popular summary of the paper "The Universe in Consciousness" by Bernardo Kastrup, Journal of Consciousness Studies, Volume 25, Numbers 5-6, 2018, pp. 125-155(31).

Kastrups reply to Pigliucci can be found here: "The remarkable criticism of Massimo Pigliucci", bernardokastrup.com, August 5 2018. From which:

The JCS summary reads:

I propose an idealist ontology that makes sense of reality in a more parsimonious and empirically rigorous manner than mainstream physicalism, bottom-up panpsychism, and cosmopsychism. The proposed ontology also offers more explanatory power than these three alternatives, in that it does not fall prey to the hard problem of consciousness, the combination problem, or the decombination problem, respectively. It can be summarized as follows: there is only cosmic consciousness. We, as well as all other living organisms, are but dissociated alters of cosmic consciousness, surrounded by its thoughts. The inanimate world we see around us is the extrinsic appearance of these thoughts. The living organisms we share the world with are the extrinsic appearances of other dissociated alters.

One wonders how a universal Mind-at-large relates to us, "as well as all other living organisms", being "but dissociated alters of cosmic consciousness". How is the connection made? What is this Mind-at-large doing elsewhere in the universe? Many grandiose claims based on a highly speculative metaphysics, for which we have zero empirical evidence.






Comment Form is loading comments...